Saturday, August 17, 2019
Locke and Hobbes
What is politics? Merriam-Webster dictionary defines it as ââ¬Å"the total complex ofà relations between people living in society.â⬠This phrase is the root of all politics and allà government. Whether we are ruler or subject, in the end we are all just ââ¬Å"people.â⬠And how canà ââ¬Å"peopleâ⬠best relate to each other? Over the years, countless individuals believed that theyà possessed the magic answer to this age-old question. Two figures in particular have endured theà praise and the criticisms: Thomas Hobbes and John Locke. Each man represents a philosophyà that has marked him in history and in the popular consciousness. And each man offers hisà unique commentaryââ¬âalong with some surprising commonalitiesââ¬âon this abstract word we callà politics. How should an affective government approach its duties and functions? John Locke and Thomas Hobbes did hold some similar viewpoints on governmentââ¬â¢s responsibilities. Both men favored a social contract between government and its people (Baker, 2000). Hobbes stated in Leviathan, ââ¬Å"Whensoever a man transferreth his right, or renounceth it, it is either in consideration of some right reciprocally transferred to himself, or for some other good he hopeth for thereby.â⬠In other words, a man must be willing to sacrifice some of his basic rights in exchange for a promise of security and stability from his government. Ever since Moses and Biblical times, Hobbes points out, Man has operated on a contract system (Panagia, 2003). Likewise, John Locke also advocated this precursor to federalism (Baker, 2000): ââ¬Å"men, when they enter into society give up â⬠¦ liberty of a kind; yet it being only with an intention in every one the better to preserve himself, his liberty and propertyâ⬠¦.â⬠(Locke, 2001) Locke believed that entering into such a covenant with government officials would best serve a ââ¬Å"common goodâ⬠and serve to create a ââ¬Å"common lawâ⬠ââ¬âideals which were also shared by Hobbes (Baker, 2000). Hobbes himself claimed that ââ¬Å"the point of the social contract is to orchestrate a multitude into some recognizable wholeâ⬠¦.â⬠(Hobbes, 1968). The government was dependent on the support of the people, and its ââ¬Å"legitimacyâ⬠¦stable only as long as the public continues to recommend itâ⬠(Hobbes, 1968). Once the function of a government is determined, the next question becomes, ââ¬Å"Who is theà government?â⬠On this point, Hobbes and Locke part ways. Since Hobbes held that human beings were essentially ââ¬Å"born bad,â⬠then logic would follow that they are not fit to rule themselves.à Instead, they need ââ¬Å"an overarching power to awe themâ⬠â⬠¦..likened to a sea monster, or a ââ¬Å"leviathanâ⬠(Geib, 2002). Hobbes argued for a single-person leadership by claiming that multiple voices of authority created ââ¬Å"too much diffidenceâ⬠(or difference). Such confusion would inevitably plunge mankind back into a primitive state of warfare, the very condition it sought to eradicate through laws and government (Kreis, 2005): ââ¬Å"for powers divided mutually destroy each otherâ⬠(Hobbes, 1968). Hobbes had witnessed firsthand the conflicts between the English king and Parliament, which hurled that country into a state of near-civil war (Chodorow, 1994). War and conflict resulted from every manââ¬â¢s universal need for power. When one puts such strong egos into one room, resolution can never hope to be obtained. To Hobbesââ¬â¢ thinking, an entrustment of the power to one individual was the best way to ensure stability. And a monarchy, with its fixed and non-debatable succession of rulers, was Hobbesââ¬â¢ preferred choice of government (Panagia, 2003). Although Hobbes anticipated such democratic mantras as ââ¬Å"the right to remain silentâ⬠and the ââ¬Å"right to property,â⬠his association with democracy affectively ends there. His absolute monarchy refutes the people as a sovereign power, and his concerns for individual liberty are miniscule (Gray, 2003).à In fact, Hobbesââ¬â¢ conservative views infuriated John Locke to such a degree that he published his own Treatises of Government, advocating a public-run government based on the liberty of the citizen. Locke raged that Hobbesââ¬â¢ monarchy left ruler and subjects in the very state of turmoil it proclaimed to avoid (Chodorow, 1994). A singular government could only serve to oppress and deny. Government should instead divide itself into branches, each serving its own specialized function while keeping the other branches from becoming too powerful (like the executive, legislative, and judicial branches of American government today). (John Locke, 2001) After all, Locke claims, the people cannot sacrifice more power than they possessed in their natural, pre-law state. Once the people enter into a social contract with their chosen government, then the sovereignty necessarily rests with the people (Landry, 1997). The people declare their leaders, and decisions rest with the ââ¬Å"consent of the majority, giving it either by themselves or their representatives chosen by themâ⬠(Locke, 2001).à The government may tax, it may allocate funds based on need (Landry, 1997), but it ââ¬Å"can never have a right to destroy, enslave, or designedly to impoverish the subjectsâ⬠(Locke, 2001). Most crucial in Lockeââ¬â¢s philosophy, the people rule. In the end, we are left with the question, ââ¬Å"Whose philosophy is best?â⬠à Give us anotherà thousand years, and we will still probably be quarrelling about the answer.à Perhaps it is best à instead to let each man have his final say on the subject and leave it at that: ââ¬Å"During the time men live without a common power to keep them all in awe, they are in that conditions called war; and such a war, as if of every man, against every man.â⬠ââ¬â(Hobbes, 1968) ââ¬Å"It is a power that hath no other end but preservation, and therefore can never have a right to destroy, enslave, or designedly to impoverish the subjects..â⬠.ââ¬â(Locke, 2001) References Baker, W. J. (2000). ââ¬Å"Faces of Federalism: From Bullinger to Jefferson.â⬠à Publius 30(4), 25. Chodorow, S. (1994). The Mainstream of Civilization. 6th ed. Fort Worth: The Harcourt Press Geib, R. (2002). Thomas Hobbes. Retrieved October 24, 2006, from The Pessimists Page: http://www.rjgeib.com/thoughts/nature/hobbes-bio.html Gray, J. (2003). ââ¬Å"The beast stirs.â⬠New Statesman 132(4634), 50-51. Hobbes, T. (1968).à Leviathan.à C.B. MacPherson, ed.à Harmondsworth:à Penguin. John Locke. (2001). Retrieved October 24, 2006, fromà Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy: http://www.utm.edu/research/iep/l/locke.htm Kreis, S. (2005). Lectures on modern intellectual history:à Thomas Hobbes. Retrieved October 24, 2006, from The History Guide: http://www.historyguide.org/intellect/hobbes.html Landry, P. (1997). John Locke (1632-1704). Retrieved October 24, 2006, from Biographies: http://www.blupete.com/Literature/Biographies/Philosophy/Locke.htm Locke, J. (2001). Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration. Penguin Classics: New York. Panagia, D. (2003). Delicate discriminations: Thomas Hobbes's science of politics. Polity 36 (1), 91-114. ; ; ; ; ;
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.